Ethics in a
Bottle
In my last blog I listed a number of statements and
underlying attitudes I encountered while working in the business world. Here I
would like to take a closer look at one of them and evaluate its veracity and
possible transformation.
The assertion that “there is no ethics in the business
world” is both an observation as also an assumption. As an observation it
reflects a simple “is”: personal experiences I shared with you in past postings
revealed that human needs are indeed frequently placed behind the short-term
imperative of a corporation to post profits and maximize shareholder wealth. In
a world where organizational survival is dictated by the mere string of numbers
that are published on a monthly or quarterly basis and not by the reality of
the personal stories of the involved stakeholders, it is only logical that
there will – push come to shove – be an inherent bias and managerial recompense
to sacrifice human “ethics” for the sake of the ethic of maximizing
profitability. Therefore, there is a certain amount of veracity to this
statement as an observation, provided one defines “ethics” as placing the
well-being of human beings in the center of our moral considerations.
As an assumption, on the other hand, this statement
implies a normative “should”: there should
not be any ethical considerations that impede the profitability and shareholder
wealth. An individual who once shared this view with me in an unabashed manner
revealed also that he made a clear cut distinction between how he valued, and consequently
then treated, people in his private circles such as friends and family, and how
he did so in his work dealings. This type of an attitude I have come to label
“ethics in a bottle”: it is a form of moral compartmentalization where at times
radically different standards apply in different types of social contexts. Now,
it is naïve to think that we as human beings can ever completely transcend
moral compartmentalization (for example, we will continue to be more inclined
to help a personal friend in distress, rather than an anonymous individual at
the other end of the world, all other things being equivalent). Nonetheless, it
is legitimate to question if such a strict demarcation line should be drawn
between the personal and professional worlds.
The problem with moral compartmentalization in our
economic dealings is that under the guise of “professionalism” almost anything can
be justified. Professional organizations and corporations, particularly
publically traded ones subject to short-term shareholder wealth maximization,
have gone to great lengths to legitimize their institutionalized norms to
conform to the prerogatives of profitability or the stock markets. Under the
guise of “accreditations”, “codes of professional conduct”, “best practices”
and the likes, professional organizations and corporations have created
sophisticated constructs to make employees, clients and the public think and
feel as if they were upholding the highest of moral standards.
For the professional, the rationale then is often, “if
it meets the highest standards of professional codes of conduct, well, than it
must be ok for me to do.”
Well, no. Simply because something meets the standards
or regulations of a certain corporation, industry or profession, does not make
it morally palatable in a larger context. For example, nowhere in the Certified
Financial Advisors (CFA) Code of Ethics (http://tinyurl.com/9wxs38)
is there any mention or consideration of the secondary ramifications of certain
investment tools or choices. Yes, we find the statement that the advisors must
“Place the integrity of the investment profession and the interests of clients
above their own personal interests.” (As recent scandals, however, illustrate that
this rule was nevertheless frequently ignored.). But what about the fact, for
example, that speculating in mercantile exchanges can abruptly drive up the
price of certain commodities like corn, wheat or rice beyond the capacity of
people in third world countries to pay for? Or take the code of conduct in
private banking, for example, of Singapore (http://tinyurl.com/bu8m8yl).
The transfer of large amounts of wealth of high net worth individuals from
poor, developing countries into international tax havens such as Singapore, the
Cayman Islands or Switzerland, while certainly in the interests of the client,
deprives these countries of these sorely needed resources. While there is
mention of money laundering and terrorism, nowhere in its code of conduct is
there any consideration of this wider moral dimension of the professional’s
actions.
However, since a financial advisor’s or private
banker’s circle of professional responsibility is defined only in a very narrow
manner driven by the client’s (and the advisor’s or bank’s) interests, both the
financial professional and their clients indirectly partake in the creation of
human poverty, and that with a clear conscience, extracted as they are of
further responsibility by the professional code of conduct they are adhering to
(and often also legitimized by Milton Freedman’s position that these ethical
consideration is not the purview of the business community, but of the
regulatory agencies of countries). This divorce of responsibility of one’s personal,
professional activities and the wider social ramifications represents one of
the major challenges facing our current status quo in how we structure and
manage our economic activities.What we consequently have is “ethics in a bottle” and by extension, if you will, a form of the “banality of evil”. It’s time for professionals to take the ethics out of the bottle and permit it to imbue all domains of human lives, not just the ones of one’s family, friends, corporation or business clients.
Manuel Heer Dawson
No comments:
Post a Comment